- Sosialisme demokratis
- Kerajaan Italia di bawah Fasisme (1922-1943)
- Egalitarian rule
- Egalitarianism
- Fractional approval voting
- Fair division of a single homogeneous resource
- Tyranny of the majority
- Golden Rule
- British Raj
- Political egalitarianism
- Social choice theory
- Cooperative bargaining
egalitarian rule
Video: egalitarian rule
Egalitarian rule GudangMovies21 Rebahinxxi LK21
In social choice and operations research, the egalitarian rule (also called the max-min rule or the Rawlsian rule) is a rule saying that, among all possible alternatives, society should pick the alternative which maximizes the minimum utility of all individuals in society. It is a formal mathematical representation of the egalitarian philosophy. It also corresponds to John Rawls' principle of maximizing the welfare of the worst-off individual.
Definition
Let
X
{\displaystyle X}
be a set of possible `states of the world' or `alternatives'. Society wishes to choose a single state from
X
{\displaystyle X}
. For example, in a single-winner election,
X
{\displaystyle X}
may represent the set of candidates; in a resource allocation setting,
X
{\displaystyle X}
may represent all possible allocations.
Let
I
{\displaystyle I}
be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each
i
∈
I
{\displaystyle i\in I}
, let
u
i
:
X
⟶
R
{\displaystyle u_{i}:X\longrightarrow \mathbb {R} }
be a utility function, describing the amount of happiness an individual i derives from each possible state.
A social choice rule is a mechanism which uses the data
(
u
i
)
i
∈
I
{\displaystyle (u_{i})_{i\in I}}
to select some element(s) from
X
{\displaystyle X}
which are `best' for society. The question of what 'best' means is the basic question of social choice theory. The egalitarian rule selects an element
x
∈
X
{\displaystyle x\in X}
which maximizes the minimum utility, that is, it solves the following optimization problem:
= Leximin rule
=Often, there are many different states with the same minimum utility. For example, a state with utility profile (0,100,100) has the same minimum value as a state with utility profile (0,0,0). In this case, the egalitarian rule often uses the leximin order, that is: subject to maximizing the smallest utility, it aims to maximize the next-smallest utility; subject to that, maximize the next-smallest utility, and so on.
For example, suppose there are two individuals - Alice and George, and three possible states: state x gives a utility of 2 to Alice and 4 to George; state y gives a utility of 9 to Alice and 1 to George; and state z gives a utility of 1 to Alice and 8 to George. Then state x is leximin-optimal, since its utility profile is (2,4) which is leximin-larger than that of y (9,1) and z (1,8).
The egalitarian rule strengthened with the leximin order is often called the leximin rule, to distinguish it from the simpler max-min rule.
The leximin rule for social choice was introduced by Amartya Sen in 1970, and discussed in depth in many later books.: sub.2.5
Properties
= Conditions for Pareto efficiency
=The leximin rule is Pareto-efficient if the outcomes of every decision are known with certainty. However, by Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem, any leximin function is Pareto-inefficient for a society that must make tradeoffs under uncertainty: There exist situations in which every person in a society would be better-off (ex ante) if they were to take a particular bet, but the leximin rule will reject it (because some person might be made worse off ex post).
= Pigou-Dalton property
=The leximin rule satisfies the Pigou–Dalton principle, that is: if utility is "moved" from an agent with more utility to an agent with less utility, and as a result, the utility-difference between them becomes smaller, then resulting alternative is preferred.
Moreover, the leximin rule is the only social-welfare ordering rule which simultaneously satisfies the following three properties:: 266
Pareto efficiency;
Pigou-Dalton principle;
Independence of common utility pace - if all utilities are transformed by a common monotonically-increasing function, then the ordering of the alternatives remains the same.
Egalitarian resource allocation
The egalitarian rule is particularly useful as a rule for fair division. In this setting, the set
X
{\displaystyle X}
represents all possible allocations, and the goal is to find an allocation which maximizes the minimum utility, or the leximin vector. This rule has been studied in several contexts:
Division of a single homogeneous resource;
Fair subset sum problem;
Egalitarian cake-cutting;
Egalitarian item allocation.
Egalitarian (leximin) bargaining.
See also
Utilitarian rule - a different rule that emphasizes the sum of utilities rather than the smallest utility.
Proportional-fair rule
Max-min fair scheduling - max-min fairness in process scheduling.
Regret (decision theory)
Wald's maximin model