- Source: Choice function
A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function f that is defined on some collection X of nonempty sets and assigns some element of each set S in that collection to S by f(S); f(S) maps S to some element of S. In other words, f is a choice function for X if and only if it belongs to the direct product of X.
An example
Let X = { {1,4,7}, {9}, {2,7} }. Then the function f defined by f({1, 4, 7}) = 7, f({9}) = 9 and f({2, 7}) = 2 is a choice function on X.
History and importance
Ernst Zermelo (1904) introduced choice functions as well as the axiom of choice (AC) and proved the well-ordering theorem, which states that every set can be well-ordered. AC states that every set of nonempty sets has a choice function. A weaker form of AC, the axiom of countable choice (ACω) states that every countable set of nonempty sets has a choice function. However, in the absence of either AC or ACω, some sets can still be shown to have a choice function.
If
X
{\displaystyle X}
is a finite set of nonempty sets, then one can construct a choice function for
X
{\displaystyle X}
by picking one element from each member of
X
.
{\displaystyle X.}
This requires only finitely many choices, so neither AC or ACω is needed.
If every member of
X
{\displaystyle X}
is a nonempty set, and the union
⋃
X
{\displaystyle \bigcup X}
is well-ordered, then one may choose the least element of each member of
X
{\displaystyle X}
. In this case, it was possible to simultaneously well-order every member of
X
{\displaystyle X}
by making just one choice of a well-order of the union, so neither AC nor ACω was needed. (This example shows that the well-ordering theorem implies AC. The converse is also true, but less trivial.)
Choice function of a multivalued map
Given two sets X and Y, let F be a multivalued map from X to Y (equivalently,
F
:
X
→
P
(
Y
)
{\displaystyle F:X\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}(Y)}
is a function from X to the power set of Y).
A function
f
:
X
→
Y
{\displaystyle f:X\rightarrow Y}
is said to be a selection of F, if:
∀
x
∈
X
(
f
(
x
)
∈
F
(
x
)
)
.
{\displaystyle \forall x\in X\,(f(x)\in F(x))\,.}
The existence of more regular choice functions, namely continuous or measurable selections is important in the theory of differential inclusions, optimal control, and mathematical economics. See Selection theorem.
Bourbaki tau function
Nicolas Bourbaki used epsilon calculus for their foundations that had a
τ
{\displaystyle \tau }
symbol that could be interpreted as choosing an object (if one existed) that satisfies a given proposition. So if
P
(
x
)
{\displaystyle P(x)}
is a predicate, then
τ
x
(
P
)
{\displaystyle \tau _{x}(P)}
is one particular object that satisfies
P
{\displaystyle P}
(if one exists, otherwise it returns an arbitrary object). Hence we may obtain quantifiers from the choice function, for example
P
(
τ
x
(
P
)
)
{\displaystyle P(\tau _{x}(P))}
was equivalent to
(
∃
x
)
(
P
(
x
)
)
{\displaystyle (\exists x)(P(x))}
.
However, Bourbaki's choice operator is stronger than usual: it's a global choice operator. That is, it implies the axiom of global choice. Hilbert realized this when introducing epsilon calculus.
See also
Axiom of countable choice
Axiom of dependent choice
Hausdorff paradox
Hemicontinuity
Notes
References
This article incorporates material from Choice function on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.
Kata Kunci Pencarian:
- SpongeBob SquarePants
- F(x) (grup musik)
- Pentet
- Ekonomika institusi
- Filsafat ilmu
- Konsumsi antarwaktu
- Gagal ginjal akut
- Hati nurani
- Hijab
- PlayStation 3
- Choice function
- Social welfare function
- Axiom of choice
- Social choice theory
- Choice
- Surjective function
- Axiom of countable choice
- Axiom of determinacy
- Wave function
- Measurable function