• Source: Ping-pong lemma
    • In mathematics, the ping-pong lemma, or table-tennis lemma, is any of several mathematical statements that ensure that several elements in a group acting on a set freely generates a free subgroup of that group.


      History


      The ping-pong argument goes back to the late 19th century and is commonly attributed to Felix Klein who used it to study subgroups of Kleinian groups, that is, of discrete groups of isometries of the hyperbolic 3-space or, equivalently Möbius transformations of the Riemann sphere. The ping-pong lemma was a key tool used by Jacques Tits in his 1972 paper containing the proof of a famous result now known as the Tits alternative. The result states that a finitely generated linear group is either virtually solvable or contains a free subgroup of rank two. The ping-pong lemma and its variations are widely used in geometric topology and geometric group theory.
      Modern versions of the ping-pong lemma can be found in many books such as Lyndon & Schupp, de la Harpe, Bridson & Haefliger and others.


      Formal statements




      = Ping-pong lemma for several subgroups

      =
      This version of the ping-pong lemma ensures that several subgroups of a group acting on a set generate a free product. The following statement appears in Olijnyk and Suchchansky (2004), and the proof is from de la Harpe (2000).
      Let G be a group acting on a set X and let H1, H2, ..., Hk be subgroups of G where k ≥ 2, such that at least one of these subgroups has order greater than 2.
      Suppose there exist pairwise disjoint nonempty subsets X1, X2, ...,Xk of X such that the following holds:

      For any i ≠ s and for any h in Hi, h ≠ 1 we have h(Xs) ⊆ Xi.
      Then





      H

      1


      ,

      ,

      H

      k



      =

      H

      1






      H

      k


      .


      {\displaystyle \langle H_{1},\dots ,H_{k}\rangle =H_{1}\ast \dots \ast H_{k}.}



      Proof


      By the definition of free product, it suffices to check that a given (nonempty) reduced word represents a nontrivial element of



      G


      {\displaystyle G}

      . Let



      w


      {\displaystyle w}

      be such a word of length



      m

      2


      {\displaystyle m\geq 2}

      , and let



      w
      =



      i
      =
      1


      m



      w

      i


      ,


      {\displaystyle w=\prod _{i=1}^{m}w_{i},}

      where




      w

      i




      H


      α

      i






      {\textstyle w_{i}\in H_{\alpha _{i}}}

      for some




      α

      i



      {
      1
      ,

      ,
      k
      }


      {\textstyle \alpha _{i}\in \{1,\dots ,k\}}

      . Since



      w


      {\textstyle w}

      is reduced, we have




      α

      i




      α

      i
      +
      1




      {\displaystyle \alpha _{i}\neq \alpha _{i+1}}

      for any



      i
      =
      1
      ,

      ,
      m

      1


      {\displaystyle i=1,\dots ,m-1}

      and each




      w

      i




      {\displaystyle w_{i}}

      is distinct from the identity element of




      H


      α

      i






      {\displaystyle H_{\alpha _{i}}}

      . We then let



      w


      {\displaystyle w}

      act on an element of one of the sets




      X

      i




      {\textstyle X_{i}}

      . As we assume that at least one subgroup




      H

      i




      {\displaystyle H_{i}}

      has order at least 3, without loss of generality we may assume that




      H

      1




      {\displaystyle H_{1}}

      has order at least 3. We first make the assumption that




      α

      1




      {\displaystyle \alpha _{1}}

      and




      α

      m




      {\displaystyle \alpha _{m}}

      are both 1 (which implies



      m

      3


      {\displaystyle m\geq 3}

      ). From here we consider



      w


      {\displaystyle w}

      acting on




      X

      2




      {\displaystyle X_{2}}

      . We get the following chain of containments:




      w
      (

      X

      2


      )




      i
      =
      1


      m

      1



      w

      i


      (

      X

      1


      )




      i
      =
      1


      m

      2



      w

      i


      (

      X


      α

      m

      1




      )




      w

      1


      (

      X


      α

      2




      )


      X

      1


      .


      {\displaystyle w(X_{2})\subseteq \prod _{i=1}^{m-1}w_{i}(X_{1})\subseteq \prod _{i=1}^{m-2}w_{i}(X_{\alpha _{m-1}})\subseteq \dots \subseteq w_{1}(X_{\alpha _{2}})\subseteq X_{1}.}


      By the assumption that different




      X

      i




      {\displaystyle X_{i}}

      's are disjoint, we conclude that



      w


      {\displaystyle w}

      acts nontrivially on some element of




      X

      2




      {\displaystyle X_{2}}

      , thus



      w


      {\displaystyle w}

      represents a nontrivial element of



      G


      {\displaystyle G}

      .
      To finish the proof we must consider the three cases:

      if




      α

      1


      =
      1
      ,


      α

      m



      1


      {\displaystyle \alpha _{1}=1,\,\alpha _{m}\neq 1}

      , then let



      h


      H

      1



      {

      w

      1



      1


      ,
      1
      }


      {\displaystyle h\in H_{1}\setminus \{w_{1}^{-1},1\}}

      (such an



      h


      {\displaystyle h}

      exists since by assumption




      H

      1




      {\displaystyle H_{1}}

      has order at least 3);
      if




      α

      1



      1
      ,


      α

      m


      =
      1


      {\displaystyle \alpha _{1}\neq 1,\,\alpha _{m}=1}

      , then let



      h


      H

      1



      {

      w

      m


      ,
      1
      }


      {\displaystyle h\in H_{1}\setminus \{w_{m},1\}}

      ;
      and if




      α

      1



      1
      ,


      α

      m



      1


      {\displaystyle \alpha _{1}\neq 1,\,\alpha _{m}\neq 1}

      , then let



      h


      H

      1



      {
      1
      }


      {\displaystyle h\in H_{1}\setminus \{1\}}

      .
      In each case,



      h
      w

      h


      1




      {\displaystyle hwh^{-1}}

      after reduction becomes a reduced word with its first and last letter in




      H

      1




      {\displaystyle H_{1}}

      . Finally,



      h
      w

      h


      1




      {\displaystyle hwh^{-1}}

      represents a nontrivial element of



      G


      {\displaystyle G}

      , and so does



      w


      {\displaystyle w}

      . This proves the claim.


      = The Ping-pong lemma for cyclic subgroups

      =
      Let G be a group acting on a set X. Let a1, ...,ak be elements of G of infinite order, where k ≥ 2. Suppose there exist disjoint nonempty subsets

      of X with the following properties:

      ai(X − Xi–) ⊆ Xi+ for i = 1, ..., k;
      ai−1(X − Xi+) ⊆ Xi– for i = 1, ..., k.
      Then the subgroup H = ⟨a1, ..., ak⟩ ≤ G generated by a1, ..., ak is free with free basis {a1, ..., ak}.


      Proof


      This statement follows as a corollary of the version for general subgroups if we let Xi = Xi+ ∪ Xi− and let Hi = ⟨ai⟩.


      Examples




      = Special linear group example

      =
      One can use the ping-pong lemma to prove that the subgroup H = ⟨A,B⟩ ≤ SL2(Z), generated by the matrices




      A
      =


      (



      1


      2




      0


      1



      )




      {\displaystyle A={\begin{pmatrix}1&2\\0&1\end{pmatrix}}}

      and



      B
      =


      (



      1


      0




      2


      1



      )




      {\displaystyle B={\begin{pmatrix}1&0\\2&1\end{pmatrix}}}


      is free of rank two.


      Proof


      Indeed, let H1 = ⟨A⟩ and H2 = ⟨B⟩ be cyclic subgroups of SL2(Z) generated by A and B accordingly. It is not hard to check that A and B are elements of infinite order in SL2(Z) and that





      H

      1


      =
      {

      A

      n



      n


      Z

      }
      =

      {



      (



      1


      2
      n




      0


      1



      )


      :
      n


      Z


      }



      {\displaystyle H_{1}=\{A^{n}\mid n\in \mathbb {Z} \}=\left\{{\begin{pmatrix}1&2n\\0&1\end{pmatrix}}:n\in \mathbb {Z} \right\}}


      and





      H

      2


      =
      {

      B

      n



      n


      Z

      }
      =

      {



      (



      1


      0




      2
      n


      1



      )


      :
      n


      Z


      }

      .


      {\displaystyle H_{2}=\{B^{n}\mid n\in \mathbb {Z} \}=\left\{{\begin{pmatrix}1&0\\2n&1\end{pmatrix}}:n\in \mathbb {Z} \right\}.}


      Consider the standard action of SL2(Z) on R2 by linear transformations. Put





      X

      1


      =

      {



      (



      x




      y



      )





      R


      2


      :

      |

      x

      |

      >

      |

      y

      |


      }



      {\displaystyle X_{1}=\left\{{\begin{pmatrix}x\\y\end{pmatrix}}\in \mathbb {R} ^{2}:|x|>|y|\right\}}


      and





      X

      2


      =

      {



      (



      x




      y



      )





      R


      2


      :

      |

      x

      |

      <

      |

      y

      |


      }

      .


      {\displaystyle X_{2}=\left\{{\begin{pmatrix}x\\y\end{pmatrix}}\in \mathbb {R} ^{2}:|x|<|y|\right\}.}


      It is not hard to check, using the above explicit descriptions of H1 and H2, that for every nontrivial g ∈ H1 we have g(X2) ⊆ X1 and that for every nontrivial g ∈ H2 we have g(X1) ⊆ X2. Using the alternative form of the ping-pong lemma, for two subgroups, given above, we conclude that H = H1 ∗ H2. Since the groups H1 and H2 are infinite cyclic, it follows that H is a free group of rank two.


      = Word-hyperbolic group example

      =
      Let G be a word-hyperbolic group which is torsion-free, that is, with no nonidentity elements of finite order. Let g, h ∈ G be two non-commuting elements, that is such that gh ≠ hg. Then there exists M ≥ 1 such that for any integers n ≥ M, m ≥ M the subgroup H = ⟨gn, hm⟩ ≤ G is free of rank two.


      Sketch of the proof


      The group G acts on its hyperbolic boundary ∂G by homeomorphisms. It is known that if a in G is a nonidentity element then a has exactly two distinct fixed points, a∞ and a−∞ in ∂G and that a∞ is an attracting fixed point while a−∞ is a repelling fixed point.
      Since g and h do not commute, basic facts about word-hyperbolic groups imply that g∞, g−∞, h∞ and h−∞ are four distinct points in ∂G. Take disjoint neighborhoods U+, U–, V+, and V– of g∞, g−∞, h∞ and h−∞ in ∂G respectively.
      Then the attracting/repelling properties of the fixed points of g and h imply that there exists M ≥ 1 such that for any integers n ≥ M, m ≥ M we have:

      gn(∂G – U–) ⊆ U+
      g−n(∂G – U+) ⊆ U–
      hm(∂G – V–) ⊆ V+
      h−m(∂G – V+) ⊆ V–
      The ping-pong lemma now implies that H = ⟨gn, hm⟩ ≤ G is free of rank two.


      Applications of the ping-pong lemma


      The ping-pong lemma is used in Kleinian groups to study their so-called Schottky subgroups. In the Kleinian groups context the ping-pong lemma can be used to show that a particular group of isometries of the hyperbolic 3-space is not just free but also properly discontinuous and geometrically finite.
      Similar Schottky-type arguments are widely used in geometric group theory, particularly for subgroups of word-hyperbolic groups and for automorphism groups of trees.
      The ping-pong lemma is also used for studying Schottky-type subgroups of mapping class groups of Riemann surfaces, where the set on which the mapping class group acts is the Thurston boundary of the Teichmüller space. A similar argument is also utilized in the study of subgroups of the outer automorphism group of a free group.
      One of the most famous applications of the ping-pong lemma is in the proof of Jacques Tits of the so-called Tits alternative for linear groups. (see also for an overview of Tits' proof and an explanation of the ideas involved, including the use of the ping-pong lemma).
      There are generalizations of the ping-pong lemma that produce not just free products but also amalgamated free products and HNN extensions. These generalizations are used, in particular, in the proof of Maskit's Combination Theorem for Kleinian groups.
      There are also versions of the ping-pong lemma which guarantee that several elements in a group generate a free semigroup. Such versions are available both in the general context of a group action on a set, and for specific types of actions, e.g. in the context of linear groups, groups acting on trees and others.


      References




      See also


      Free group
      Free product
      Kleinian group
      Tits alternative
      Word-hyperbolic group
      Schottky group

    Kata Kunci Pencarian: