- Source: Proof (truth)
A proof is sufficient evidence or a sufficient argument for the truth of a proposition.
The concept applies in a variety of disciplines,
with both the nature of the evidence or justification and the criteria for sufficiency being area-dependent. In the area of oral and written communication such as conversation, dialog, rhetoric, etc., a proof is a persuasive perlocutionary speech act, which demonstrates the truth of a proposition. In any area of mathematics defined by its assumptions or axioms, a proof is an argument establishing a theorem of that area via accepted rules of inference starting from those axioms and from other previously established theorems. The subject of logic, in particular proof theory, formalizes and studies the notion of formal proof. In some areas of epistemology and theology, the notion of justification plays approximately the role of proof, while in jurisprudence the corresponding term is evidence,
with "burden of proof" as a concept common to both philosophy and law.
In most disciplines, evidence is required to prove something. Evidence is drawn from the experience of the world around us, with science obtaining its evidence from nature, law obtaining its evidence from witnesses and forensic investigation, and so on. A notable exception is mathematics, whose proofs are drawn from a mathematical world begun with axioms and further developed and enriched by theorems proved earlier.
Exactly what evidence is sufficient to prove something is also strongly area-dependent, usually with no absolute threshold of sufficiency at which evidence becomes proof. In law, the same evidence that may convince one jury may not persuade another. Formal proof provides the main exception, where the criteria for proofhood are ironclad and it is impermissible to defend any step in the reasoning as "obvious" (except for the necessary ability of the one proving and the one being proven to, to correctly identify any symbol used in the proof.); for a well-formed formula to qualify as part of a formal proof, it must be the result of applying a rule of the deductive apparatus of some formal system to the previous well-formed formulae in the proof sequence.
Proofs have been presented since antiquity. Aristotle used the observation that patterns of nature never display the machine-like uniformity of determinism as proof that chance is an inherent part of nature. On the other hand, Thomas Aquinas used the observation of the existence of rich patterns in nature as proof that nature is not ruled by chance.
Proofs need not be verbal. Before Copernicus, people took the apparent motion of the Sun across the sky as proof that the Sun went round the Earth. Suitably incriminating evidence left at the scene of a crime may serve as proof of the identity of the perpetrator. Conversely, a verbal entity need not assert a proposition to constitute a proof of that proposition. For example, a signature constitutes direct proof of authorship; less directly, handwriting analysis may be submitted as proof of authorship of a document. Privileged information in a document can serve as proof that the document's author had access to that information; such access might in turn establish the location of the author at certain time, which might then provide the author with an alibi.
Proof vs evidence
18th-century Scottish philosopher David Hume built on Aristotle's separation of belief from knowledge, recognizing that one can be said to "know" something only if one has firsthand experience with it, in a strict sense proof, while one can infer that something is true and therefore "believe" it without knowing, via evidence or supposition. This speaks to one way of separating proof from evidence:
If one cannot find their chocolate bar, and sees chocolate on their napping roommate's face, this evidence can cause one to believe their roommate ate the chocolate bar. But they do not know their roommate ate it. It may turn out that the roommate put the candy away when straightening up, but was thus inspired to go eat their own chocolate. Only if one directly experiences proof of the roommate eating it, perhaps by walking in on them doing so, would one have certain knowledge, in Hume's sense, that the roommate did it.
In a more strict sense of sure knowledge, one may be unable to prove anything to a rational certainty beyond that of the existence of one's immediate sensory awareness. Descartes famously raised a similarly strict standard with his first principle Cogito, ergo sum (I think, therefore I am). While Descartes' larger project in Meditations on First Philosophy has knowledge of God and the external world—founded on the certainty of the cogito—as its aim, his legacy in doing so is to have shown that one cannot have such proof, because all perceptions could be false (such as under the evil demon or simulated reality hypotheses). One nevertheless can still have clear proof of the existence of one's thought, even if belief in the external world lacks the certainty of demonstration beyond that of one's own firsthand experience.
See also
Mathematical proof
Proof theory
Proof of concept
Provability logic
Evidence, information which tends to determine or demonstrate the truth of a proposition
Proof procedure
Proof complexity
Standard of proof
References
Kata Kunci Pencarian:
- Lawrence Bender
- The Fundamentals
- Antisemitisme rasial
- Pembunuhan Muhammad ad-Durrah
- Rosa Salazar
- LeBron James
- Daftar karakter Game of Thrones
- Amanda Tapping
- Mata uang kripto
- Teorema ketaklengkapan Gödel
- Proof (truth)
- Proof
- Formal proof
- Proof by contradiction
- Method of analytic tableaux
- Proof theory
- Burden of proof (law)
- Zero-knowledge proof
- Mathematical proof
- Direct proof