- Source: Well-ordering theorem
In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set X is well-ordered by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of X has a least element under the ordering. The well-ordering theorem together with Zorn's lemma are the most important mathematical statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice (often called AC, see also Axiom of choice § Equivalents). Ernst Zermelo introduced the axiom of choice as an "unobjectionable logical principle" to prove the well-ordering theorem. One can conclude from the well-ordering theorem that every set is susceptible to transfinite induction, which is considered by mathematicians to be a powerful technique. One famous consequence of the theorem is the Banach–Tarski paradox.
History
Georg Cantor considered the well-ordering theorem to be a "fundamental principle of thought". However, it is considered difficult or even impossible to visualize a well-ordering of
R
{\displaystyle \mathbb {R} }
; such a visualization would have to incorporate the axiom of choice. In 1904, Gyula Kőnig claimed to have proven that such a well-ordering cannot exist. A few weeks later, Felix Hausdorff found a mistake in the proof. It turned out, though, that in first-order logic the well-ordering theorem is equivalent to the axiom of choice, in the sense that the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of choice included are sufficient to prove the well-ordering theorem, and conversely, the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms without the axiom of choice but with the well-ordering theorem included are sufficient to prove the axiom of choice. (The same applies to Zorn's lemma.) In second-order logic, however, the well-ordering theorem is strictly stronger than the axiom of choice: from the well-ordering theorem one may deduce the axiom of choice, but from the axiom of choice one cannot deduce the well-ordering theorem.
There is a well-known joke about the three statements, and their relative amenability to intuition:The axiom of choice is obviously true, the well-ordering principle obviously false, and who can tell about Zorn's lemma?
Proof from axiom of choice
The well-ordering theorem follows from the axiom of choice as follows.Let the set we are trying to well-order be
A
{\displaystyle A}
, and let
f
{\displaystyle f}
be a choice function for the family of non-empty subsets of
A
{\displaystyle A}
. For every ordinal
α
{\displaystyle \alpha }
, define an element
a
α
{\displaystyle a_{\alpha }}
that is in
A
{\displaystyle A}
by setting
a
α
=
f
(
A
∖
{
a
ξ
∣
ξ
<
α
}
)
{\displaystyle a_{\alpha }\ =\ f(A\smallsetminus \{a_{\xi }\mid \xi <\alpha \})}
if this complement
A
∖
{
a
ξ
∣
ξ
<
α
}
{\displaystyle A\smallsetminus \{a_{\xi }\mid \xi <\alpha \}}
is nonempty, or leave
a
α
{\displaystyle a_{\alpha }}
undefined if it is. That is,
a
α
{\displaystyle a_{\alpha }}
is chosen from the set of elements of
A
{\displaystyle A}
that have not yet been assigned a place in the ordering (or undefined if the entirety of
A
{\displaystyle A}
has been successfully enumerated). Then the order
<
{\displaystyle <}
on
A
{\displaystyle A}
defined by
a
α
<
a
β
{\displaystyle a_{\alpha }
if and only if
α
<
β
{\displaystyle \alpha <\beta }
(in the usual well-order of the ordinals) is a well-order of
A
{\displaystyle A}
as desired, of order type
sup
{
α
∣
a
α
is defined
}
{\displaystyle \sup\{\alpha \mid a_{\alpha }{\text{ is defined}}\}}
.
Proof of axiom of choice
The axiom of choice can be proven from the well-ordering theorem as follows.
To make a choice function for a collection of non-empty sets,
E
{\displaystyle E}
, take the union of the sets in
E
{\displaystyle E}
and call it
X
{\displaystyle X}
. There exists a well-ordering of
X
{\displaystyle X}
; let
R
{\displaystyle R}
be such an ordering. The function that to each set
S
{\displaystyle S}
of
E
{\displaystyle E}
associates the smallest element of
S
{\displaystyle S}
, as ordered by (the restriction to
S
{\displaystyle S}
of)
R
{\displaystyle R}
, is a choice function for the collection
E
{\displaystyle E}
.
An essential point of this proof is that it involves only a single arbitrary choice, that of
R
{\displaystyle R}
; applying the well-ordering theorem to each member
S
{\displaystyle S}
of
E
{\displaystyle E}
separately would not work, since the theorem only asserts the existence of a well-ordering, and choosing for each
S
{\displaystyle S}
a well-ordering would require just as many choices as simply choosing an element from each
S
{\displaystyle S}
. Particularly, if
E
{\displaystyle E}
contains uncountably many sets, making all uncountably many choices is not allowed under the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice.
Notes
External links
Mizar system proof: http://mizar.org/version/current/html/wellord2.html
Kata Kunci Pencarian:
- Hermann Weyl
- Well-ordering theorem
- Well-order
- Well-ordering principle
- Georg Cantor
- Well-quasi-ordering
- Zorn's lemma
- Kruskal's tree theorem
- Ernst Zermelo
- Schröder–Bernstein theorem
- Axiom of choice