- Source: A. C. Ewing
Alfred Cyril Ewing FBA ( YOO-ing; 11 May 1899 – 14 May 1973) was an English philosopher who spent most of his career at the University of Cambridge. He was a prolific writer who made contributions to Kant scholarship, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophy of religion.
Biography
Alfred Ewing was born in Leicester, England, on 11 May 1899, the only child of Emma and H. F. Ewing. He was educated at Wyggeston Grammar School.
From his entrance to University College, Oxford, Ewing's early academic career was, as Russell Grice remarks, one of "almost unparalleled brilliance." Firsts in Classical Moderations and, in 1920, 'Greats' were followed by a Bishop Fraser Scholarship at Oriel College in 1920 and a Senior Demyship at Magdalen College in 1921 He was awarded the John Locke Scholarship in Mental Philosophy (now the John Locke Prize) the same year.
In 1923, Ewing was amongst the first Oxford students to be awarded a DPhil, his (revised) thesis being published as Kant's Treatment of Causality (1924). He served as a lecturer at Oxford 1924 –1925, He was awarded the Green Prize in Moral Philosophy in 1926. An expanded version of the essay for which he won the same was published as The Morality of Punishment (1929), with a short introduction by W. D. Ross.
After holding temporary positions at Michigan University (in the summer session of 1926) and Armstrong College, Newcastle-upon-Tyne (in 1927), he served as a lecturer in philosophy at University College, Swansea from 1927 until 1931.
In 1931 he was appointed University Lecturer in Moral Science at Cambridge. (A. J. Ayer describes him being as being 'imported' to teach the history of philosophy.) Ewing would later recall his "shock" on arriving at Cambridge to find "dominant not the influence of Moore, Broad, or Russell, but the influence of Wittgenstein" reporting that "the reaction his philosophy provoked in me was one of sharp antagonism."
He was awarded, the Cambridge D.Litt in 1933, at the remarkably early age of 34. The following year, Ewing published his extensive study Idealism: A Critical Survey, which was reviewed favourably by T. E. Jessop. And offers an early characterisation of a 'traditional account' of coherentist epistemic justification.
The late 1930s saw the publication of "Meaninglessness" and 'The Linguistic Theory' two "powerfully argued" papers that, Brand Blanshard contends, "must have contributed much to the disintegration of positivism."
He served as president of the Aristotelian Society from 1941 to 1942, and was elected a Fellow of the British Academy in 1941. He delivered the latter's annual Henriette Hertz philosophical lecture the same year. During the Second World War, Goebel records, Ewing turned his attention back to ethics with the publication of a series of articles that formed the basis of two works both published in 1947:The Definition of Good (an investigation primarily into problems of metaethics) and The Individual, the State, and World Government (a work on political ethics against the background of the European catastrophe and the danger of nuclear war).
Two visiting professorships took him to Princeton and Northwestern University in 1949. In the winter of 1950 Ewing attended the silver jubilee Indian Philosophical Congress in Calcutta and lectured at a number of Indian universities. He returned to India in 1959, to Mysore, to attend the joint symposium between the Indian Philosophical Congress and the International Institute of Philosophy, of which he was an active member.
At Cambridge where, as Ayer contends, Ewing was "not well treated," he was "eventually" made a reader in 1954. And, after many years of lecturing for the university, he was finally elected a fellow of Jesus College in 1962, As Ayer, notes. Ewing "was an able philosopher, a good scholar and a prolific writer" but one that "never caught the idiom . . largely foisted on Cambridge in the 1930s by Ludwig Wittgenstein."
After holding a visiting position in Colorado in 1963, he retired from Cambridge in 1966 with an Honorary Fellowship from Jesus College. and moved to Manchester. But in 1967 he took a visiting position at San Francisco State College and in 1971 such a post at Delaware.
He continued to write, working to complete Value and Reality: the Philosophical Case for Theism (1973) which was published posthumously. This was a work, Grice records, Ewing "had started writing for twenty-five years before its publication," and one "that had been his central concern for the last five years of his life."
Ewing died of a stroke in Manchester, England, on 14 May 1973. He left his papers, and Goebel reports, his body, to the University of Manchester. His eyes went to Manchester Royal Eye Hospital and the rest to Manchester anatomy department. To "the Moral Science Library in SIdgwick Avenue, Cambridge, he left his picture of Kant."
Ayer recalls teasing the devout and "unswervingly honest" Ewing with the question of what he was most looking forward to in the afterlife, His immediate response being that "God will tell me whether there are synthetic a priori propositions."
Blanshard paid tribute to Ewing in both a journal obituary, and within his own Library of Living Philosophers Festschrift.
Thomas Hurka notes that "Grice's fine obituary of him is poignant, describing a man whose work was not appreciated at its true worth because of a change in philosophical fashion—and the arrogance of those who made the change—and irrelevant facts about his personality" but "that as parts of moral philosophy return to views like Ewing's his contributions are becoming better known."
Philosophical work
Ewing was a defender of traditional metaphysics (as opposed to post-modern ethics) and developed what has been termed an "analytic idealism".
He was one of the foremost analysts of the concept "good", and a distinguished contributor to justificatory theorizing about punishment.
Ewing was critical of the verification theory of meaning. He held the view that probability was not a quality of a thing, preferring to understand it in relative terms. Any probability statement without implicit or explicit reference to the relevant data upon which probability is based was considered meaningless.
Additionally he viewed self-contradictions to be meaningful. He said that although there is "a sense in which it seems reasonable to say that all self-contradictory sentences are meaningless" in that we cannot "combine" the meaningful constituents of self-contradictions in thought, there is also a sense in which they are meaningful. He therefore took issue with the thesis that "we cannot think the meaning of a self-contradictory statement as a whole, though we know the meaning of the separate words". A self-contradiction, according to Ewing, proposes that two ideas can be combined into one, which is a proposition. If self-contradictions were meaningless and a "mere set of words" then we would not be able to investigate or say if they were wrong, and it is this proposition that they can be combined which makes a self-contradictory utterance meaningful.
Ewing distinguished between two forms of philosophical analysis. The first is "what the persons who make a certain statement usually intend to assert" and the second "the qualities, relations and species of continuants mentioned in the statement". As an illustration he takes the statement "I see a tree", this statement could be analysed in terms what the everyday person intends when they say this or it could be analysed metaphysically by asserting representationalism.
Works
= Books
=Kant's Treatment of Causality. London: Kegan Paul, 1924.
The Morality of Punishment. with Suggestions for a General Theory of Ethics, London: Kegan Paul, 1929. reprinted with a new preface, Montclair, N.J.: Patterson Smith, 1970
Idealism: A Critical Survey. London: Methuen, 1934. (New edition, 1961.)
A Short Commentary on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason". London: Methuen, 1938. (New edition, 1950.)
Reason and Intuition. London: Humphrey Milford, 1941.
The Individual, the State, and World Government. New YorK: Macmillan, 1947.
The Definition of Good. New York: Macmillan, 1947; London: Routledge, Kegan Paul, 1948.
The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951. (New edition, London: Routledge, 1980.)
Ethics. London: English Universities Press, 1953. (New editions, New York: Free Press, 1965; London: Teach Yourself Books, 1975.)
(ed.) The Idealist Tradition: from Berkeley to Blanshard; edited, with an introduction and commentary. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1957.
Second Thoughts in Moral Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959. (New edition, 2012.)
Non-linguistic Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1968.
Value and Reality: the Philosophical Case for Theism. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1973
= Select papers/book chapters
=(1923) "Kant's Transcendental Deduction of the Categories" Mind, 32, (125): 50–66
(1925)."The Relation Between Knowing and its Object (I.)"Mind. 34 (134): 137–153
(1925) "The Relation Between Knowing and Its Object (II.)" Mind, 34 (135): 300–310.
(1927) "Punishment as a Moral Agency: An Attempt to Reconcile the Retributive and the Utilitarian View" Mind 36 (143): 292–305;
(1929) "The Idea of Cause" Journal of Philosophical Studies. 4 (16): 453–466
(1931) "The Message of Kant". Journal of Philosophical Studies. 6 (21): 43–55
(1932) "A Defence of Causality". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 33: 95–128, reprinted in Kennick, W. E. (ed.) Metaphysics: Readings and Reappraisals (1966) pp. 258–275
(1937) "Meaninglessness". Mind. 46 (183): 347–364. excerpted in Edwards, Paul & Arthur Pap (eds.) A Modern Introduction to Philosophy (1965) [1957], a very much abbreviated form of this article contributed by Ewing, along with a brief 1961 addendum, can be found in MacGregor, Geddes & Robb, J. Wesley (eds) Readings in religious philosophy (1962).
(1939). "The Linguistic Theory of "A Priori" Propositions". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 40: 207–244.
(1943) "Punishment as Viewed by the Philosopher" The Canadian Bar Review, 21
(1944) "Subjectivism and Naturalism in Ethics" Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210, pp. 120–141, reprinted in: Sellars and Hospers (eds.), Readings in Ethical Theory, pp. 118–133 (1957)
(1947) "Kantianism" in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.) Twentieth Century Philosophy: Living Schools of Thought pp. 251–264
(1949) "Philosophical Ethics and the Ethics of Practical Life" in Proceedings of the Tenth International Congress of Philosophy 1:470–472
(1953)."Empiricism in Ethics". Proceedings of the XIth International Congress of Philosophy 10 pp. 78–82.
(1953) "The Necessity Of Metaphysics," in H. D. Lewis (ed.) Contemporary British Philosophy. Personal Statements. Third series
(1954) "Kant's Attack on Metaphysics". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 8 (30 (4)): 371–391
(1955) "Recent Tendencies in Moral Philosophy in Great Britain" Zeitschrift Für Philosophische Forschung, vol. 9, no. 2, pp. 337–47.
(1957) "Recent Developments in British Ethical Thought," in C. A. Mace (ed.), British Moral Philosophy in the Mid-Century, London: George Allen & Unwin, pp. 63–95.
(1961) "The Autonomy of Ethics" in: Ian Ramsey (ed.), Prospect for Metaphysics. Essays of Metaphysical Exploration, pp. 33–49
(1968) "The Concept of Democracy" in: World Perspectives in Philosophy, Religion, and Culture
(1968) "C.I. Lewis on the Relation Between the Good and the Right" in Schilpp, P. A. (ed.) The Philosophy of C. I. Lewis (The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 13). Open Court.
(1970) "Christian Ethics and Utilitarianism" in R. L. Cunningham (ed.), Situationism and The New Morality, New York, 152–167
(1975) "My Philosophical Attitude" in Philosophers on Their Own Work, vol. 1 (in a series published under the auspices of the International Federation of Philosophical Societies.
(1980) "Blanshard's View of Good" in Schilpp, P. A. (ed.) The Philosophy of Brand Blanshard (The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 15).
*More complete publication details can be found online in Bernd Goebel's entry on Ewing for the BBKL.
Notes
References
Sources
Grice, G. R. (1975). "Alfred Cyril Ewing, 1899–1973" (PDF). Proceedings of the British Academy. 59 (1973): 499–513.
Goebel, Bernd (2014). "Einleitung" (PDF). Ethik: eine Einführung (in German). (Introductory essay to a translation of Ewing's Ethics.)
Further reading
Binkley, Luther J., "III. A. C. Ewing: "Ought" as the Basic Ethical Term,"Contemporary Ethical Theories. (1961)
R.D. Geivett, "Ewing, Alfred Cyril" in: T.A. Hart (ed.), The Dictionary of Historical Theology (2000) pp. 200–201 ISBN 9781842270028
Thomas Hurka (ed.), Underivative Duty: British Moral Philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing (Oxford, 2011) ISBN 9780191792694
Hurka, Thomas, "Common Themes from Sidgwick to Ewing" author pre-print, published version: doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199577446.003.0002
Olson, Jonas, and Mark Timmons, 'A. C. Ewing's First and Second Thoughts in Metaethics', author pre-print, published version: doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199577446.003.0011,
Goebel, Bernd (2010). "Alfred Cyril Ewing". Biographisch-Bibliographisches Kirchenlexikon (in German). Vol. 31. pp. 414–424. ISBN 978-3-88309-544-8.
External links
Brand Blanshard "Alfred Cyril Ewing, 1899–1973" (Archived),
Kata Kunci Pencarian:
- Daftar tempat di Alabama/A-L
- Britania Raya
- Maude Adams
- Daftar mineralog
- Daftar Duta Besar Amerika Serikat untuk Siprus
- Jesse Metcalfe
- New York Knicks
- Penggali parit
- Cloud Atlas (film)
- Hugues IV dari Maine
- A. C. Ewing
- Rodney C. Ewing
- George C. Ewing
- Maria Ewing
- John C. Ewing
- Ewing sarcoma
- Raymond C. Ewing
- J. C. Ewing
- Patrick Ewing
- Ewing (surname)